Learning is a fundamental process of life as the ultimate
point of learning is to allow an individual to function effectively. It allows
the individual to adapt behaviour to the social and cultural norms of the
community. The definition of the concept has been a matter of philosophical
discussions from the time of Socrates. All human activities and achievements
manifest the result of learning. Whether we regard life in terms of the race,
or of community, or the individual, we are faced on every side by the pervasive
effects of learning. Since learning is such a fundamental process of life, it
has been the prey of philosophers whose essential activity is to question the
accepted ‘truths’ and received wisdom.
Vessey (1964) defines learning as ‘the acquisition of
something by a process other than maturation’ and maturation as ‘the developing
of readiness’ to perform certain actions without being taught. This is
psychological rather than philosophical definition. However, one way of knowing
whether learning has taken place is that the individual is able to demonstrate
the possession of appropriate knowledge. Yet, philosophically, the question:
‘What is knowledge?’ remains problematic (Magee 1987). It is clear however that
the process of learning involves what Hilgarde (cited by Langford 1969) regards
as originating in the individual reacting to an encountered situation. Piaget
(1970) affirms that, an individual from childhood builds mental
maps/concepts/schemes for understanding and responding to the physical experience
in his environment.
Thus, in reacting to our daily experiences, learning plays a
crucial role in ensuring appropriate responses. For this to happen, it is clear
that what we need is flexible rather than fixed habits. (figure 1) Hence
learning must enable the individual to be in command of a repertoire of
procedures or behaviours, each of which may be employed smoothly, habitually
and efficiently.
Figure 1
As with all philosophical questions, the nature of learning
itself requires careful thought in order to obtain a clear understanding of the
concept. Hardie (1962) states ‘the only source of true learning is direct
experience of nature through our own sense impression’. But the term ‘nature’
is capable of a number of interpretations. The French philosopher Rousseau
(1712 – 1778) was reputed to have used it in no less than three different ways
as noted by Langford (1969). Consequently, as Langford argues, until its
precise meaning has been determined, it is impossible to decide whether the
nature of learning has meaning or is merely a catch phrase or emotional
‘rallying point’.
However, the most important of Rousseau’s interpretation of
the concept ‘nature’ means to use his own words, ‘the internal development of
our senses’ which is more than the psychologists mean when they use the term
‘maturation’ or ‘readiness to perform certain acts without prior teaching’.
Hardie (1962) states that ‘learning ought to enable a child to develop
according to the laws of his own nature’. It could be argued that this means a
child should be able to grow mentally and physically. Thus if this natural
process of mental and physical development is maturation, then learning must not
only allow it to occur but it must facilitate it.
An important philosophical question in this regard is the
relationship between mind and learning. Can mind give clarity and substance for
a better understanding of learning? Mind is generally conceived as being
characterised by awareness of thinking. In psychological terms it is cognitive
in that it engages in complex processing of thinking. It is also interpretive
in that it takes input from the outside world into the conscious mind and
transforms it into functional units of belief and understanding at different
levels in the mind. If the conscious mind is responsible for thought then it
could be argued that learning could only occur in the waking state.
All such questions raise difficult philosophical issues. If
learning is part of the thinking process, then the notion of learning itself
must not be taken for granted. As Wittgenstein is said to have warned: ‘don’t
just take it for granted, but think’ (Magee 1987).
For example, can learning occur during the unconscious
state, as during the unaware period of sleep? Or is it just sensations and
feelings in the mind of past experiences or a form of reinforcement from the
awake period of learning? These are important philosophical questions. Locke
(cited Russell 1961) argues that the mind at birth maybe considered like a
white paper void of all characteristics (tabula rasa). He, therefore, wondered
how it could be furnished with endless variety of all the materials of reason
and knowledge. His celebrated answer to the question is ‘open experience’. That
is all our knowledge is found on and ultimately derived from experience.
(figure 2)
In general, it is argued that our ideas are derived from two
sources, that of sensation and the perception of the operation of our mind. The
latter may be called our ‘internal senses’. Since we can only think by means of
ideas, and since all ideas come from experience, it is evident that none of our
knowledge can ante-date experience. The fundamental question is whether man is born
with a mental structure that influences his perception right from the beginning
or with a mind that is essentially as what Locke argued, ‘a open tabula rasa’.
It should be noted that Russell in ‘An Inquiry in Meaning and Truth’ (1973)
argued that the word ‘perception’ is inappropriate to describe our beliefs
because it is suggested that such beliefs are true. Locke argued that we should
describe them instead as ‘experience’ as Russell notes. ‘Thus whenever I think
I can see a cat, I have the perceptive experience of ‘seeing a cat’, even if,
on this occasion no physical cat is present.’
Figure 2
The view that reasoning or thought is a central factor in
learning is known as ‘rationalism’. Rationalists are of the opinion that the
raw data of sensation must be organised by the mind into meaningful patterns
before anything worthy of the name learning is used. What the individual knows
are meaningful ideas, conceptions and principles. Moreover, if thought is a
central factor in learning then it would seem reasonable to suppose that
thought alone would be the source of important aspects of learning. The more
controversial aspect of rationalism, however, has to do with the meaning of the
expression ‘thought’ apart from the sense experience.
In philosophical terminology, the question is usually posed
as, what is the ‘nature of prior learning?’ This is important because,
traditionally, prior learning was said to be gained, by reasoning from
self-evident principles without dependence of anything gained from sense
experience. It was set, in contrast to later learning which, is attained by
reasoning from the impressions gained through observation or other sense
experience. The view that all knowledge comes through the senses is known as
‘empiricism’. Locke and before him, Descartes are acknowledged empiricists in
philosophy (Ayers in Magee 1987). These views are given further credibility by
our increasing knowledge of neuroscience as the nervous system with the brain,
are the physical foundations of the process of learning. Neuroscience links
cognitive behaviour with the physical processes that support such behaviour.
The importance of prior learning and memory is confirmed by the finding that
brain changes with use throughout the lifetime. Memory is formed, by
strengthening certain patterns of neuro-connections, as we use our brains. This
makes it easier to create connections the next time. So learning is about
promoting complex thinking and growth of the brain. (Sylwester 1993)
It may be that the term learning is being applied to more
than one thing, but that it is treated as if it were one thing? In education, learning
is invariably used as a ‘blank term’. Lewin (cited by Moore 1974) describes
learning as four types of activities.
The first is cognitive when we become aware of the facts and
information at an intellectual level. In this, we gain knowledge and understanding.
The second he sees as, motivational when we change to the level of goals and
values. The third is ideological and is not unlike the second but more at the
level of values and attitudes. Finally, the fourth has to do with body control
such as acquiring a skill, which involves physical manipulation which
highlights the genetic nature of learning and links it to maturation.
It would seem, therefore, that real learning is the sum of
all the activities that are operating in any specific situation. Thus learning
is more than the sum of our cognitive, affective and behavioural activities.
Real learning occurs when the learner exercises and realises the potential
activity of the cognitive, affective or emotional behavioural levels. When
these activities take place in interactive individual or group situation, then
the resultant activity or change will represent learning. It can be said that
learning is a three dimensional phenomenon having real significance only when
it operates in these three dimensions.
Traditionally the formal learning in educational
institutions emphasises on cognitive and psychomotor skills learning. Academic
success is based on intelligence measured by IQ using standardised tests.
However, the use of this is limited within the workplace. Recent researches
emphasise on a need to develop and focus on affective learning, that is,
emotional intelligence. Emotional health is fundamental to effective learning
according to research into brain based learning, for happy people are more apt to
retain information and do so more effectively than unhappy people.
Emotional intelligence becomes even more vital as knowledge
is rapidly expanding and this leads to change in all spheres of life.
Individuals have to be therefore able to learn and adapt equally rapidly. For
Goleman (1998, pp 4) states that ‘the concept of a ‘job’ is rapidly being
replaced by ‘portable skills’ for they ‘are prime qualities that make and keep
us employable’. So success in life is no longer ensured by just possessing knowledge
but by the ability to learn, by understanding how to learn.
No comments:
Post a Comment